up:: π₯ Sources
type:: #π₯/π°
status:: #π₯/π₯
tags:: #on/articles
topics:: Aristotle, Philosophy
Author:: Jared Henderson
Title:: So that we may become good - Nicomachean Ethics Book II
URL:: "https://jaredhenderson.substack.com/p/so-that-we-may-become-good-nicomachean?r=1t9e3k&utm_medium=ios&triedRedirect=true"
Reviewed Date:: 2025-03-04
Finished Year:: 2025
So that we may become good - Nicomachean Ethics, Book II
summary:: A summary and analysis of Book 2 of Nicomachean Ethics. Through habituation and conscious choice, individuals can cultivate moral virtues, which lie as a mean between two vices, guiding them towards virtuous actions and judgments.
Take a look at all of my highlights, denoted here by unique ids. Ignore the single word highlights, some contain definitions below them, those can be combined in a "Words" list with definitions of each which we will do later. Given the other highlights, and the personal notes I made below them for some of them, give me a short essay describing the themes of the article, use quotes from the highlights and include outside sources if you find it helpful.
Thoughts
Highlights
id859711051
Intellectual and moral virtues π
id859711090
there are two different sorts of virtues: intellectual and moral. The intellectual virtues are wisdom and prudence. π
id859711096
The moral virtues are things like justice, courage, and moderation. π
id859711155
Intellectual virtues are taught, requiring time and experience. (So they are not merely acquired by being told once or twice about them.) Moral virtues are habituated. Indeed, the word for moral virtue in Greek, ΔthikΔ, is a slight alteration of ethos, the word for habit. π
id859711180
The virtues are not present in us by nature; we are not born virtuous. Rather, we are born with the capacity for virtue. These capacities need to be developed. π
id859711259
one becomes virtuous by acting virtuously. But crudely, moral virtue really is βfake it until you make itβ sort of thing. π
id859711297
The role of pleasure (and a bit about the arts) π
id859711332
By acting virtuously again and again, you develop the habit of being virtuous. You also start to think virtuously, making the right sort of judgments. And importantly, you begin to take pleasure in acting virtuously. π
id859711396
virtues typically require a kind of development, and thus acting virtuously is a kind of skill. π
id859711447
it is possible to create a beautiful artistic work by chance. And that is importantly different from virtuous action. We cannot be virtuous by chance, because a truly virtuous action requires that the action be in a certain state (it being the virtuous thing to do) but also that the actor be in a certain state (thinking and judging virtuously). Virtue ethics, in general, requires that someone does the right thing for the right reason. π
id859711482
Utilitarians really only care about the right action. Kantians think you need to do it for the right reason, too. Virtue ethics, in this regard, is more similar to Kantianism than to utilitarianism. π
id859711511
So while you can perform moderate actions when you are not yourself moderate, what is really happening in this case is that you are becoming virtuous β you just arenβt there yet. π
id859711534
But whatever deeds arise in accord with the virtues are not done justly or moderately if they are merely in a certain state, but only if he who does those deeds is in a certain state as well: first, if he acts knowingly; second, if he acts by choosing and by choosing the actions in question for their own sake; and, third, if he acts while being in a steady and unwavering state π
id859711555
Virtue is the mean between vices π
id859711613
Virtue, therefore, is a characteristic marked by choice, residing in the mean relative to us, a characteristic defined by reason and as the prudent person would define it. Virtue is also a mean with respect to two vices, the one vice related to excess, the other to deficiency; and further, it is a mean because some vices fall short of and others exceed what should be the case in both passions and actions, whereas virtue discovers and chooses the middle term. Thus, with respect to its being and the definition that states what it is, virtue is a mean; but with respect to what is best and the doing of something well, it is an extreme. π
id859712370
First, virtuous action is a choice β it canβt be pure reflex or done through coercion. This is because it is a product of our rational soul. π
id859712423
Second, virtue resides in a mean βrelative to us.β The relative clause is important here, as we are not concerned with virtue for any sort of creature, but rather for us in particular. π
id859712449
Third, a virtue is a mean between two vices. Vices are excesses of action, and virtue sits somewhere between two vices. Consider courage. Courage sits between cowardice and recklessness. Cowardice and recklessness are vices, and courage is the virtue. But this does not mean courage is exactly in the middle. We are looking for the golden mean, the natural balancing point between the two vices. In the case of some virtues, one vice is much closer to the virtue than the other (like moderation is closer to insensibility than to gluttony). π
id859712497
Fourth, virtue is an extreme. You cannot be too courageous. If you are in excess, you cease to be courageous and become, say, reckless. But this isnβt because you are too courageous, but rather have deviated from courage into recklessness. This is an important point, because it allows us to say that being virtuous is always good; there is no such thing as too much of a good thing, at least when we speak of virtue. π